In August of 2012, news outlets ranging from the Washington Post to the Huffington Post ran a story about the rise of atheism in America. The source for the story was a poll that asked people, “Irrespective of whether you attend a place of worship or not, would you say you are a religious person, not a religious person or a convinced atheist?” This type of question, which asks people to classify themselves in one way or another, is common in polling and generates categorical data. In this lab we take a look at the atheism survey and explore what’s at play when making inference about population proportions using categorical data.
To access the press release for the poll, conducted by WIN-Gallup International, click on the following link:
Take a moment to review the report then address the following questions.
These percentages are sample statistics because they were derived from a data sample. The entire population was not polled.
The sample observations must be independent. That is, they must be less than 10% of the population. That seems like a reasonable assumption. The sampling method of choosing countries and individuals within countries needs to be a simple random sample. That seems like a reasonable assumption. There are at least 10 observations of each type. This is a reasonable assumption.
Turn your attention to Table 6 (pages 15 and 16), which reports the sample size and response percentages for all 57 countries. While this is a useful format to summarize the data, we will base our analysis on the original data set of individual responses to the survey. Load this data set into R with the following command.
load("more/atheism.RData")
atheism
correspond to?Each row corresponds to the the percentage of people from a country who identified as religious, not religious or an athiest.
To investigate the link between these two ways of organizing this data, take a look at the estimated proportion of atheists in the United States. Towards the bottom of Table 6, we see that this is 5%. We should be able to come to the same number using the atheism
data.
us12
that contains only the rows in atheism
associated with respondents to the 2012 survey from the United States. Next, calculate the proportion of atheist responses. Does it agree with the percentage in Table 6? If not, why?library(dplyr)
##
## Attaching package: 'dplyr'
## The following objects are masked from 'package:stats':
##
## filter, lag
## The following objects are masked from 'package:base':
##
## intersect, setdiff, setequal, union
us12 <- subset(atheism, nationality == "United States" & year == "2012")
usatheist <- subset(us12, response=="atheist")
percatheist <- count(usatheist)/count(us12)
percatheist
## n
## 1 0.0499002
This percentage has more precision than the value in table 6, but the values are consistent with each other.
As was hinted at in Exercise 1, Table 6 provides statistics, that is, calculations made from the sample of 51,927 people. What we’d like, though, is insight into the population parameters. You answer the question, “What proportion of people in your sample reported being atheists?” with a statistic; while the question “What proportion of people on earth would report being atheists” is answered with an estimate of the parameter.
The inferential tools for estimating population proportion are analogous to those used for means in the last chapter: the confidence interval and the hypothesis test.
The conditions for inference are that observations are independent and that the success-failure condition is met. There are 1032 people poled and this is less than 10% of the US’s population so that condition is met. The success-failure condition states that there are at least 10 successes and 10 failures. There were 50 atheists and 952 non-atheists so that condition is also met. The conditions for inference are met.
If the conditions for inference are reasonable, we can either calculate the standard error and construct the interval by hand, or allow the inference
function to do it for us.
inference(us12$response, est = "proportion", type = "ci", method = "theoretical",
success = "atheist")
## Warning: package 'BHH2' was built under R version 3.4.2
## Single proportion -- success: atheist
## Summary statistics:
## p_hat = 0.0499 ; n = 1002
## Check conditions: number of successes = 50 ; number of failures = 952
## Standard error = 0.0069
## 95 % Confidence interval = ( 0.0364 , 0.0634 )
Note that since the goal is to construct an interval estimate for a proportion, it’s necessary to specify what constitutes a “success”, which here is a response of "atheist"
.
Although formal confidence intervals and hypothesis tests don’t show up in the report, suggestions of inference appear at the bottom of page 7: “In general, the error margin for surveys of this kind is \(\pm\) 3-5% at 95% confidence”.
margin of error = z*SE
SE <- sqrt(.05*.95/count(us12))
margin of error = 0.0134949
inference
function, calculate confidence intervals for the proportion of atheists in 2012 in two other countries of your choice, and report the associated margins of error. Be sure to note whether the conditions for inference are met. It may be helpful to create new data sets for each of the two countries first, and then use these data sets in the inference
function to construct the confidence intervals.china12 <- subset(atheism, nationality == "China" & year == "2012")
inference(china12$response, est = "proportion", type = "ci", method = "theoretical",
success = "atheist")
## Single proportion -- success: atheist
## Summary statistics:
## p_hat = 0.47 ; n = 500
## Check conditions: number of successes = 235 ; number of failures = 265
## Standard error = 0.0223
## 95 % Confidence interval = ( 0.4263 , 0.5137 )
The margin of error is 0.0437. The conditions for inference are that observations are independent and that the success-failure condition is met. There are 500 people polled and this is less than 10% of the China’s population so that condition is met. The success-failure condition states that there are at least 10 successes and 10 failures. There were 235 atheists and 265 non-atheists so that condition is also met. The conditions for inference are met.
germany12 <- subset(atheism, nationality == "Germany" & year == "2012")
inference(germany12$response, est = "proportion", type = "ci", method = "theoretical",
success = "atheist")
## Single proportion -- success: atheist
## Summary statistics:
## p_hat = 0.1494 ; n = 502
## Check conditions: number of successes = 75 ; number of failures = 427
## Standard error = 0.0159
## 95 % Confidence interval = ( 0.1182 , 0.1806 )
The margin of error is 0.0312. The conditions for inference are that observations are independent and that the success-failure condition is met. There are 502 people polled and this is less than 10% of the Germany’s population so that condition is met. The success-failure condition states that there are at least 10 successes and 10 failures. There were 75 atheists and 427 non-atheists so that condition is also met. The conditions for inference are met.
Imagine you’ve set out to survey 1000 people on two questions: are you female? and are you left-handed? Since both of these sample proportions were calculated from the same sample size, they should have the same margin of error, right? Wrong! While the margin of error does change with sample size, it is also affected by the proportion.
Think back to the formula for the standard error: \(SE = \sqrt{p(1-p)/n}\). This is then used in the formula for the margin of error for a 95% confidence interval: \(ME = 1.96\times SE = 1.96\times\sqrt{p(1-p)/n}\). Since the population proportion \(p\) is in this \(ME\) formula, it should make sense that the margin of error is in some way dependent on the population proportion. We can visualize this relationship by creating a plot of \(ME\) vs. \(p\).
The first step is to make a vector p
that is a sequence from 0 to 1 with each number separated by 0.01. We can then create a vector of the margin of error (me
) associated with each of these values of p
using the familiar approximate formula (\(ME = 2 \times SE\)). Lastly, we plot the two vectors against each other to reveal their relationship.
n <- 1000
p <- seq(0, 1, 0.01)
me <- 2 * sqrt(p * (1 - p)/n)
plot(me ~ p, ylab = "Margin of Error", xlab = "Population Proportion")
p
and me
.The margin of error is greatest when the population proportion is 0.5 and lowest when the population proportion is 0 or 1. The rate at which the margin of error changes with the population proportion is lowest around 0.5 and greatest near 0 and 1.
The textbook emphasizes that you must always check conditions before making inference. For inference on proportions, the sample proportion can be assumed to be nearly normal if it is based upon a random sample of independent observations and if both \(np \geq 10\) and \(n(1 - p) \geq 10\). This rule of thumb is easy enough to follow, but it makes one wonder: what’s so special about the number 10?
The short answer is: nothing. You could argue that we would be fine with 9 or that we really should be using 11. What is the “best” value for such a rule of thumb is, at least to some degree, arbitrary. However, when \(np\) and \(n(1-p)\) reaches 10 the sampling distribution is sufficiently normal to use confidence intervals and hypothesis tests that are based on that approximation.
We can investigate the interplay between \(n\) and \(p\) and the shape of the sampling distribution by using simulations. To start off, we simulate the process of drawing 5000 samples of size 1040 from a population with a true atheist proportion of 0.1. For each of the 5000 samples we compute \(\hat{p}\) and then plot a histogram to visualize their distribution.
p <- 0.1
n <- 1040
p_hats <- rep(0, 5000)
for(i in 1:5000){
samp <- sample(c("atheist", "non_atheist"), n, replace = TRUE, prob = c(p, 1-p))
p_hats[i] <- sum(samp == "atheist")/n
}
hist(p_hats, main = "p = 0.1, n = 1040", xlim = c(0, 0.18))
These commands build up the sampling distribution of \(\hat{p}\) using the familiar for
loop. You can read the sampling procedure for the first line of code inside the for
loop as, “take a sample of size \(n\) with replacement from the choices of atheist and non-atheist with probabilities \(p\) and \(1 - p\), respectively.” The second line in the loop says, “calculate the proportion of atheists in this sample and record this value.” The loop allows us to repeat this process 5,000 times to build a good representation of the sampling distribution.
mean
to calculate summary statistics.summary(p_hats)
## Min. 1st Qu. Median Mean 3rd Qu. Max.
## 0.07019 0.09327 0.09904 0.09969 0.10577 0.12981
The mean of the distribution is 0.009969. The mean and median are very similar. The sample is unimodal and symmetric.
par(mfrow = c(2, 2))
command before creating the histograms. You may need to expand the plot window to accommodate the larger two-by-two plot. Describe the three new sampling distributions. Based on these limited plots, how does \(n\) appear to affect the distribution of \(\hat{p}\)? How does \(p\) affect the sampling distribution?par(mfrow = c(2, 2))
hist(p_hats, main = "p = 0.1, n = 1040", xlim = c(0, 0.18))
summary(p_hats)
## Min. 1st Qu. Median Mean 3rd Qu. Max.
## 0.07019 0.09327 0.09904 0.09969 0.10577 0.12981
p <- 0.1
n <- 400
p_hats <- rep(0, 5000)
for(i in 1:5000){
samp <- sample(c("atheist", "non_atheist"), n, replace = TRUE, prob = c(p, 1-p))
p_hats[i] <- sum(samp == "atheist")/n
}
hist(p_hats, main = "p = 0.1, n = 400", xlim = c(0, 0.18))
summary(p_hats)
## Min. 1st Qu. Median Mean 3rd Qu. Max.
## 0.05250 0.09000 0.10000 0.09976 0.11000 0.15500
p <- 0.02
n <- 1040
p_hats <- rep(0, 5000)
for(i in 1:5000){
samp <- sample(c("atheist", "non_atheist"), n, replace = TRUE, prob = c(p, 1-p))
p_hats[i] <- sum(samp == "atheist")/n
}
hist(p_hats, main = "p = 0.02, n = 1040", xlim = c(0, 0.18))
summary(p_hats)
## Min. 1st Qu. Median Mean 3rd Qu. Max.
## 0.005769 0.017308 0.020192 0.019954 0.023077 0.039423
p <- 0.02
n <- 400
p_hats <- rep(0, 5000)
for(i in 1:5000){
samp <- sample(c("atheist", "non_atheist"), n, replace = TRUE, prob = c(p, 1-p))
p_hats[i] <- sum(samp == "atheist")/n
}
hist(p_hats, main = "p = 0.02, n = 400", xlim = c(0, 0.18))
summary(p_hats)
## Min. 1st Qu. Median Mean 3rd Qu. Max.
## 0.00000 0.01500 0.02000 0.01988 0.02500 0.04750
Each of the plots for sample size 1040 is symmetric and unimodal. The plot for the smallest probability of success and only 400 observations is skewed slightly to the right. The mean for distributions of the same probability of success are about equal to each other, even when the number of observations are different. The spread is greater when the sample size is smaller. The larger the probability of a success, the larger the spread.
Once you’re done, you can reset the layout of the plotting window by using the command par(mfrow = c(1, 1))
command or clicking on “Clear All” above the plotting window (if using RStudio). Note that the latter will get rid of all your previous plots.
We should proceed with inference for the sample for Australia with a sample proportion 0f .1 and sample size of 1040. The distribution is symmetric and there are more than 10 successes and 10 failures.
We should not proceed with inference for the sample for Ecuador, which has 400 subjects and a sample proportion of 0.02. There are fewer than 10 successes. However the shape of the sampling distribution is not very skewed and the there are over 400 observations.
The question of atheism was asked by WIN-Gallup International in a similar survey that was conducted in 2005. (We assume here that sample sizes have remained the same.) Table 4 on page 13 of the report summarizes survey results from 2005 and 2012 for 39 countries.
Answer the following two questions using the inference
function. As always, write out the hypotheses for any tests you conduct and outline the status of the conditions for inference.
a. Is there convincing evidence that Spain has seen a change in its atheism index between 2005 and 2012?
Hint: Create a new data set for respondents from Spain. Form confidence intervals for the true proportion of athiests in both years, and determine whether they overlap.
spain12 <- subset(atheism, nationality == "Spain" & year == "2012")
inference(spain12$response, est = "proportion", type = "ci", method = "theoretical",
success = "atheist")
## Single proportion -- success: atheist
## Summary statistics:
## p_hat = 0.09 ; n = 1145
## Check conditions: number of successes = 103 ; number of failures = 1042
## Standard error = 0.0085
## 95 % Confidence interval = ( 0.0734 , 0.1065 )
The conditions for inference are that observations are independent and that the success-failure condition is met. There are 1145 people polled and this is less than 10% of the Spain’s population so that condition is met. The success-failure condition states that there are at least 10 successes and 10 failures. There were 103 atheists and 1042 non-atheists so that condition is also met. The conditions for inference are met.
Ho: The proportion of atheists in Spain in 2005 and 2015 are the same. \(\p_{2005} - \p_{2012}\) = 0
HA: The proportion of atheists in Spain in 2005 and 2015 are not the same. \(\p_{2005} - \p_{2012}\) \(\neq\) 0
There is not convincing evidence that Spain has seen a change in its atheism from 2005 to 2012. In 2012, we can be 95% confident that the percentage of atheists falls between 7.34% and 10.65%. In 2005 the percentage of atheists was 10%, which is within that interval. We fail to reject the null hypothesis.
b. Is there convincing evidence that the United States has seen a change in its atheism index between 2005 and 2012?
inference(us12$response, est = "proportion", type = "ci", method = "theoretical",
success = "atheist")
## Single proportion -- success: atheist
## Summary statistics:
## p_hat = 0.0499 ; n = 1002
## Check conditions: number of successes = 50 ; number of failures = 952
## Standard error = 0.0069
## 95 % Confidence interval = ( 0.0364 , 0.0634 )
The conditions for inference are that observations are independent and that the success-failure condition is met. There are 1002 people polled and this is less than 10% of the United States’ population so that condition is met. The success-failure condition states that there are at least 10 successes and 10 failures. There were 50 atheists and 952 non-atheists so that condition is also met. The conditions for inference are met.
Ho: The proportion of atheists in the United States in 2005 and 2015 are the same. \(\p_{2005} - \p_{2012}\) = 0
HA: The proportion of atheists in the United States in 2005 and 2015 are not the same. \(\p_{2005} - \p_{2012}\) \(\neq\) 0
In 2012, we can be 95% confident that the percentage of atheists in the United States falls between 3.64% and 6.34%. In 2005 the percentage of atheists in the United States was 1%, which is not within that 95% confidence interval. We reject the null hypothesis.
- If in fact there has been no change in the atheism index in the countries listed in Table 4, in how many of those countries would you expect to detect a change (at a significance level of 0.05) simply by chance?
Hint: Look in the textbook index under Type 1 error.
I would expect to detect a type 1 error 5% of of the time for a significance level of 0.05.
From the graph of margin of error vs. population proportion, I can see that a margin of error of 0.01 is associated with p = 0.025.
margin of error = z*SE
0.01 = 1.96 x \(\sqrt{p(1-p)/n}\)
0.01 = 1.96 x \(\sqrt{.025(1-.025)/n}\)
n = 936.39
You would need a sample of 937 people.
This is a product of OpenIntro that is released under a Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported. This lab was written for OpenIntro by Andrew Bray and Mine Çetinkaya-Rundel.